Justice and international affairs

A.A. 2025/2026
6
Crediti massimi
40
Ore totali
SSD
SPS/01
Lingua
Inglese
Obiettivi formativi
The course focuses on topics and questions currently at the centre of the philosophical debate on global justice. On the one hand, the course aims at familiarizing students with the basic notions and concepts crucial to make sense of questions of distributive justice as well as with the major conceptions of justice developed for the domestic level. On the other hand, the course intends to offer clues for appreciating the peculiarity of the global domain, the specific challenges connected to extending requirements of justice beyond domestic contexts, and the key arguments for and against such an extension.
Risultati apprendimento attesi
Knowledge and understanding: Students are expected to acquire a clear understanding about the key notions and concepts employed in the philosophical debate concerning distributive justice. Students are also expected to acquire in-depth knowledge concerning the major approaches to distributive justice developed for the domestic domain and to understand their assumptions and their implications for the debate on global justice. Moreover, students are expected to gain familiarity with the peculiarity of the global domain, with the challenges connected to extending requirements of justice beyond domestic contexts and with arguments for and against such an extension.
Applying knowledge and understanding: At the end of the course, students are expected to be able to apply their acquired knowledge and competences in the field of distributive justice and global justice to issues animating public debates. To this end, the course offers several occasions for in-depth class discussion, which will provide a suitable space for debating the relevance and import of the philosophical notions and approaches under examination with respect to more concrete issues and questions. Moreover, the course focuses on topics currently at the centre of public debate - such as migration and climate change - that are precisely meant to increase students' understanding about how to use abstract and general philosophical arguments to tackle more specific problems.
Making judgements: Thanks to the structure of the course and the selected readings, students are expected to increase their propensity for autonomous judgment. To this end, students will be required to read and examine essays providing opposing arguments (e.g. one essay for and one essay against a certain conception of justice) or essays endorsing different theoretical and methodological approaches. Students will be therefore introduced to a plurality of perspectives and this is expected to improve their capacity to adjudicate among conflicting arguments by autonomously assessing their relative merits and limits. Moreover, the bulk of the course will consist in the analysis of philosophical arguments - of their premises and their internal structure - and students will be required to critically examine the arguments at stake, thus further enhancing their capacity to autonomously judge their validity.
Communication: Students are expected to acquire familiarity with the argumentative strategies endorse in philosophical debates, which offer insights on how to elaborate consistent arguments or proposals and on how to effectively defend them and which are therefore functional to improve students' communication skills by. Moreover, students will be required to summarize and discuss complex arguments in a clear and effective way both orally - through in-class presentations - and in written form, thus having a further opportunity to strengthen their communication skills. For attendant students, similar skills are expected to be enhanced also through class discussions, which are meant to provide students with the opportunity to improve their argumentative capacities by engaging with arguments proposed by their classmates.
Corso singolo

Questo insegnamento può essere seguito come corso singolo.

Programma e organizzazione didattica

Edizione unica

Responsabile
Periodo
Primo trimestre

Programma
The course offers an overview of the major normative problems that concern the activity of war. Since war, by its very nature and definition, involves widespread killing and maiming, it raises among the most interesting, intricated, and complex philosophical and normative questions in the field of international affairs. Indeed, if those engaged in a war usually transgress the boundaries and limits of everyday morality, grounded in the convictions that killing and inflicting harm constitute wrongdoings, very few consider war always and totally impermissible. To understand and make sense of this paradox, the course explores classical and contemporary debates in just war theory, discussing also some historical and fictional examples to illustrate ideas and problems that pertain to the domain of war. In particular, the course tackles issues such as the conditions that are to be satisfied in order to permissibly start a war; the duties combatants have during a war; the nature and morality of terrorism; moral concerns regarding recent advances in military technology; the problem of reconstruction after a war.

Lecture 1 Political realism

Lecture 2 Self-defence and war: some methodological remarks

Lecture 3 The principles of Jus ad bellum

Lecture 4 Anticipations and interventions

Lecture 5 Presentations and discussion

Lecture 6 The principles of Jus in bello

Lecture 7 Presentations and discussion

Lecture 8 The moral status of combatants

Lecture 9 Presentations and discussion

Lecture 10 Non-combatant immunity

Lecture 11 Presentations and discussion

Lecture 12 Terrorism

Lecture 13 Presentations and discussion

Lecture 14 Remote warfare

Lecture 15 Presentations and discussion

Lecture 16 Jus post bellum

Lecture 17 Presentations and discussion

Lecture 18 Pacifism

Lecture 19 Presentations and discussion

Lecture 20 Wrap up
Prerequisiti
No specific prior knowledge is required to successfully attend the course or take the exam.
Metodi didattici
- Traditional frontal lectures
- Presentations offered by students on specific texts and cases
- Discussions of case studies and short videos
- Group discussion
Materiale di riferimento
The exam material is different for 1. attendant students and 2. non-attendant students

1. Attendant students
General readings
Walzer, Michael (1977), Just and Unjust Wars, New York: Basic Books (Ch. 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7).

Meterials for attendant students' presentations
Students are required and expected to complete the readings selected by their colleagues for presentation in advance of the relevant session in which such readings will be discussed in class.

Lecture 5: Political realism, jus ad bellum, humanitarian intervention
· Walzer, Michael (1977), "Against realism", in Just and Unjust Wars, New York: Basic Books, pp. 3-20.
· Anscombe, G.E.M. (1981), "War and Murder", in Ethics, Religion, and Politics, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press: https://philpapers.org/archive/ANSWAM.pdf

· McMahan, Jeff (2005), "Just cause for war", Ethics and International Affairs, 19, No. 3, pp. 1-21.
· Shue, Henry (2007), "What would a justified preventive military attack look like?", in H.Shue and D. Rodin (eds.), Preemption. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 222-46.
· Holder, Cindy (2008), "Responding to humanitarian crises", in L. May (ed.), War: Essays in Political Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 85-104.


Lecture 7: Jus in bello
· Nagel, Thomas (1972), "War and massacre", Philosophy and Public Affairs 1, No. 2, pp. 123-44.
· Hurka, Thomas (2005), "Proportionality in the morality of war", Philosophy and Public Affairs 33, No. 1, pp. 34-66.
Lecture 9: The moral status of combatants
· McMahan, Jeff (2006), "On the moral equality of combatants", Journal of Political Philosophy, 14, No. 2, pp. 377-93.
· Hurka, Thomas (2007), "Liability and just cause", Ethics and International Affairs, 21, No. 2, pp. 199-218.

Lecture 11: Non-combatant immunity
· May, Larry (2005), "Killing naked soldiers: distinguishing between combatants and non-combatants", Ethics and International Affairs 19, No. 3, pp. 39-53.
· Fabre, Cecile (2009), "Guns, food, and liability to attack in war", Ethics, 120, No.1, pp. 36-63.

Lecture 13: Terrorism
· Coady, Cecil A. J. (2004), "Terrorism, Morality and Supreme Emergency", Ethics, 114, No. 4, pp. 772-789.
· Scheffler, Samuel (2006), "Is terrorism morally distinctive?", Journal of Political Philosophy, 14, No. 1, pp. 1-17.
· McPherson, Lionel K. (2007), "Is terrorism distinctively wrong?", Ethics, 117, No. 3, pp. 524-46.

Lecture 15: Remote Warfare
· Killmister, S. (2008), "Remote Weaponry: The Ethical Implications", Journal of Applied Philosophy, No. 25, pp. 121-133.
· Strawser, Bradley. J. (2010), "Moral predators: the duty to employ uninhabited aerial vehicles", Journal of Military Ethics 9 (4), pp. 342-68.
· Amoroso, Daniele and Tamburrini Guglielmo (2018), "The Ethical and Legal Case Against Autonomy in Weapons Systems", Global Jurist, No. 18: art. 20170012. doi:10.1515/gj-2017-0012

Lecture 17: Jus post bellum
· Arendt, Hannah (1964) Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of Evil, New York: Penguin Classics, excerpts + Arendt, Hannah & Jaspers, Karl (1992), Hannah Arendt-Karl Jaspers Correspondence 1926-1969, New York: Mariner Books, excerpts.
· Wellman, Christopher Heath (2008), "Amnesties and international law", In Larry May (ed.), War: Essays in Political Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 249-
· Murphy, Colleen & Radzik, Linda (2013). "Jus Post Bellum and Political Reconciliation". In Larry May & Edenberg Elizabeth, Jus Post Bellum and Transitional Justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Lecture 18: Pacifism
· Narveson, J. (1965), "Pacifism: A philosophical analysis", Ethics, 75, pp. 259-271.
· Alexandra, A. (2003), "Political Pacifism", Social Theory and Practice, 29, pp. 589-606.
· Fiala, A. (2014), "Contingent Pacifism and Contingently Pacifist Conclusions" The Journal of Social Philosophy 45, pp. 463-477.


2. Non-attendant students
General readings necessary for the first part of the written test
· Korab-Karpowicz, W. Julian, "Political Realism in International Relations", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = .
· Orend, Brian, "War", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2008 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = .
· Walzer, Michael (1977), Just and Unjust Wars, New York: Basic Books (Ch. 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7).
· Frowe, Helen (2015), The Ethics of War and Peace: An Introduction, London: Routledge (Ch. 3, 4, 5, 6, 7, 8, 9, 10, 11, 12).

Specific readings for the second part of the written test
Students are required to choose one argumens from those proposed below in order to be able to answer one essay question in the second part of the written test.

Jus ad bellum
· McMahan, Jeff (2005), "Just cause for war", Ethics and International Affairs, 19, No. 3, pp. 1-21.
· Hurka, Thomas (2007), "Liability and just cause", Ethics and International Affairs, 21, No. 2, pp. 199-218.
· May, Larry (2008), "The principle of just cause", in L. May (ed.), War: Essays in Political Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 49-66.
Humanitarian intervention
· Smith, Michael (1998), "Humanitarian intervention: an overview of the ethical issues", Ethics and International Affairs, Vol. 12, No. 1, pp. 63-79.
· Holder, Cindy (2008), "Responding to humanitarian crises", in L. May (ed.), War: Essays in Political Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 85-104.
· Pattison, James (2013), "Is there a duty to intervene? Intervention and the responsibility to protect", Philosophy Compass, Vol. 8, N. 6, pp. 570-79.

Combatants and non-combatants
· McMahan, Jeff (2009), "Civilian immunity and civilian liability", in Killing in War, New York: Oxford University Press, pp. 203-35.
· Lazar, Seth (2010), "The responsibility dilemma for killing in war: a review essay", Philosophy and Public Affairs, Vol. 38, No. 2, pp. 180-213.
· Fabre, Cecile (2009), "Guns, food, and liability to attack in war", Ethics, 120, No.1, pp. 36-63.

Remote Warfare
· Killmister, S. (2008), "Remote Weaponry: The Ethical Implications", Journal of Applied Philosophy, No. 25, pp. 121-133.
· Strawser, Bradley. J. (2010), "Moral predators: the duty to employ uninhabited aerial vehicles", Journal of Military Ethics, No. 9, pp. 342-68.
· Amoroso, Daniele and Tamburrini Guglielmo (2018), "The Ethical and Legal Case Against Autonomy in Weapons Systems", Global Jurist, No. 18: art. 20170012. doi:10.1515/gj-2017-0012.

Jus post bellum
· May, Larry (2005), "Superior Orders, Duress, and Moral Perception", in Crimes Against Humanity: a normative account. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 170-200.
· Wellman, Christopher Heath (2008), "Amnesties and international law", In Larry May (ed.), War: Essays in Political Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 249-65.
· Brian Orend (2007), "Jus post bellum: the perspective of a just-war theorist", Leiden Journal of International Law, 20, pp. 571-91.

Pacifism
· Fiala, Andrew, "Pacifism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2023 Edition), Edward N. Zalta & Uri Nodelman (eds.), URL = .
· Narveson, J. (1965), "Pacifism: A philosophical analysis", Ethics, 75, pp. 259-271.
· Alexandra, A. (2003), "Political Pacifism", Social Theory and Practice, 29, pp. 589-606.
Modalità di verifica dell’apprendimento e criteri di valutazione
The exam structure is different for 1. attendant and 2. non-attendant students.

1. Attendant students
Attendant students are expected, not just to attend classes, but also to actively participate in the discussions of the topics and texts under investigation. Students' participation is evaluated by taking into account students' contribution to class discussion. In this manner, students are encouraged to develop and exercise their argumentative capacities and to actively analyse and discuss the arguments relevant for the topics under consideration, providing reasons and justifications for their claims and evaluations.

Students are also evaluated on the basis of their presentations. Students are required to summarize and discuss the central arguments advanced within texts that are selected in advanced by the responsible. In this way, students are encouraged to advance and expand not only their communicative and organizational skills, but also their capacities to understand, evaluate and critically examine the validity of philosophical and normative arguments in an autonomous and independent manner.

Finally, students are required to deliver a paper (3.000 words) on one of the topics discussed during the course and in agreement with the responsible of the course. Papers should represent a piece of independent research, be it a positive argument of one's own, or a critical argument meant to challenge the position of an author discussed during the course. Papers should provide clear and coherent claims apt to defend a position, through the evaluation of its problems and merits.

Final grades will be awarded by weighting participation, presentation and final paper as follow:
· 25% Participation
· 35% Presentations
· 40% Final paper

Criteria of assessment:
First Class (27-30 cum laude)
Participation: The student consistently contributes with insightful, well-articulated points that reflect a deep understanding of the readings and issues discussed. Contributions are analytically rigorous, well-supported with reasons, and often help advance or clarify class discussions.

Presentation: The presentation is clearly structured, focused, and demonstrates an excellent grasp of the text and its arguments. The student not only explains the author's position accurately but also offers thoughtful critical reflections, showing an ability to assess arguments independently. The presentation is engaging and shows strong communicative and organizational skills.
Final Paper: The paper addresses a clearly defined research question or problem, shows originality of thought, and is structured around a coherent argumentative line. The student engages critically and autonomously with the relevant literature, offering well-developed, well-supported arguments. Writing is clear, precise, and stylistically mature.

Upper Second Class (25-26)
Participation: The student participates regularly with relevant and coherent contributions that show a solid understanding of the material. There is some engagement with argumentation and independent thought, though not consistently at an advanced level.
Presentation: The presentation covers the main points of the text accurately and clearly. Some effort is made to evaluate arguments and engage critically with the material. The structure is generally clear and delivery is competent, if occasionally lacking in depth or originality.
Final Paper: The paper is well-organized and demonstrates a clear understanding of the topic. The student engages with the relevant literature and presents a solid argument. There is some degree of critical analysis, though the argumentation may lack depth or sophistication in places.

Lower Second Class (22-24)
Participation: The student participates occasionally and shows a basic understanding of the material. Contributions are generally accurate but may lack depth, clarity, or a critical dimension. Engagement tends to be more reactive than proactive.
Presentation: The presentation conveys the main ideas of the assigned text but lacks analytical depth. The structure may be unclear at times, and critical reflection is limited. The student demonstrates some understanding, but argumentation is underdeveloped.
Final Paper: The paper meets the basic requirements of the assignment and shows a fair grasp of the topic. The structure is present but may be inconsistent or unclear in places. Critical engagement is minimal, and arguments may be vague or insufficiently supported by reasons or references.

Third Class (18-21)
Participation: Participation is minimal and reflects only a basic or superficial understanding of the course material. Comments may be unclear, off-topic, or merely paraphrase class discussions without further contribution.
Presentation: The presentation is poorly structured or lacks coherence. The student struggles to convey the main arguments of the text or does so inaccurately. Little to no critical engagement is present, and communication may be unclear or hesitant.
Final Paper: The paper shows some effort, but understanding of the topic is limited. Arguments are often unclear or unsupported. The use of literature is minimal or incorrect. The paper may lack structure and demonstrate significant difficulties in critical reasoning and argumentative writing.

Fail (0-17)
Participation: No meaningful participation.
Presentation: The presentation is missing or so incomplete that it fails to demonstrate any meaningful understanding of the assigned text. Major misunderstandings are evident, and there is no critical engagement.
Final Paper: The paper fails to address the topic adequately. It shows no understanding of key concepts or texts, lacks argumentation, and contains serious factual or interpretative errors. It may be incoherent, poorly written, or incomplete.

2. Non-attendant students
Non-attendant students are required to take a written exam constituted by two parts. In the first part, students are asked to answer five open questions regarding the major problems and basic notions of just war theory. This part of the written exam is meant to ascertain the acquisition of appropriate knowledge and understanding of the topics addressed in the general readings assigned.

In the second part of the written test, students are required to answer one essay question of their choice, among a group. This part of the test is concerned with the specific readings suggested. Indeed, students need to choose one topic of their interest among "jus ad bellum"; "humanitarian intervention"; "combatants and non-combatants"; "remote warfare"; "just post bellum"; "pacifism" in order to write one short essay apt to demonstrate their capacity to tackle and discuss controversial topics concerning the debates about the ethics of war, by assessing and evaluating different and competing arguments.
Important: If a student fails three or more answers in Part 1, the essay in Part 2 will not be evaluated, and the overall exam will be considered a fail.

Criteria of assessment:
First Class (27-30 cum laude)
Part 1
Responses show a clear, precise, and thorough understanding of the key problems and basic notions of the debates covered by the course. Answers demonstrate knowledge, conceptual clarity, and the ability to explain relationships between ideas. Terminology is used accurately, and responses are well-structured, accurate, and appropriate.
Part 2
The essay is clearly structured, conceptually sophisticated, and critically engaged. The student accurately reconstructs relevant arguments from the readings and engages in a thoughtful and well-supported assessment of competing views. The writing reflects independence of thought, logical clarity, and an ability to evaluate complex ethical questions. The essay goes beyond description to offer critical insights and cogent reasoning, supported by relevant sources.

Upper Second Class (25-26)
Part 1
Answers are mostly accurate and show a good understanding of the major concepts and problems. Responses are clear and organized, with relevant use of terminology. There may be some inaccuracies or slight gaps in explanation, but overall, the student shows solid knowledge and understanding.
Part 2
The essay is well-structured and demonstrates a good grasp of the topic. Relevant positions are explained clearly and compared appropriately. There is some level of critical engagement and independent reasoning, though it may lack depth or originality. Arguments are generally well-supported, with correct references to the readings.

Lower Second Class (22-24)
Part 1
Answers show a basic but uneven understanding of the key ideas. Essential concepts are mentioned but may be presented with vagueness, limited clarity, or occasional confusion. Use of terminology may be inconsistent. Some responses may lack completeness or depth.
Part 2
The essay addresses the question but remains largely descriptive. The student identifies relevant arguments or positions but struggles to evaluate them critically. The structure may be uneven, and the argument underdeveloped. There may be limited engagement with the readings or insufficient support for claims.

Third Class (18-21)
Part 1
Answers indicate limited familiarity with core ideas and concepts. There may be several inaccuracies, unclear formulations, or failure to fully address the question. Some key terms may be misused or left undefined.
Part 2
The essay shows little critical engagement and lacks clear structure. Arguments are vague or poorly supported. There may be misunderstanding of key positions or significant errors. The writing may be disorganized and show minimal engagement with the readings.

Fail (0-17)
Part 1
Answers are missing, incorrect, or show serious misunderstandings. The student demonstrates little to no knowledge of the material. Responses may be confused, off-topic, or incoherent.
Part 2
The essay is either missing or fails to address the question. It may contain substantial factual or conceptual errors and show no critical engagement. The argument is incoherent or entirely absent. Use of readings is minimal, incorrect, or nonexistent.
SPS/01 - FILOSOFIA POLITICA - CFU: 6
Lezioni: 40 ore
Docente/i
Ricevimento:
Nel mese di luglio, il ricevimento si tiene solo online e senza una data fissa. Il prossimo ricevimento si terrà mercoledì 23 luglio dalle 15 alle 18.
Il ricevimento si svolge online (via MS Teams), o in presenza (Dip. Scienze sociali e politiche, II piano, stanza 205) o in presenza su prenotazione (Dip. Scienze sociali e politiche, II piano, stanza 205).